Mercurial > emacs
annotate etc/WHY-FREE @ 83436:f67e432d150c
Fix crash in lookup_image on termcap frames.
* src/xdisp.c (get_glyph_string_clip_rects): Add extra parentheses and
braces to prevent compiler warnings.
(calc_pixel_width_or_height): Add xassert to check that the
frame is alive. Don't call `lookup_image' on a termcap frame.
* image.c (lookup_image): Don't initialize `c' until the xasserts have
been run.
git-archimport-id: lorentey@elte.hu--2004/emacs--multi-tty--0--patch-476
author | Karoly Lorentey <lorentey@elte.hu> |
---|---|
date | Fri, 30 Dec 2005 05:29:31 +0000 |
parents | 23a1cea22d13 |
children |
rev | line source |
---|---|
49600
23a1cea22d13
Trailing whitespace deleted.
Juanma Barranquero <lekktu@gmail.com>
parents:
25853
diff
changeset
|
1 Why Software Should Not Have Owners |
25853 | 2 |
3 by Richard Stallman | |
4 | |
5 Digital information technology contributes to the world by making it | |
6 easier to copy and modify information. Computers promise to make this | |
7 easier for all of us. | |
8 | |
9 Not everyone wants it to be easier. The system of copyright gives | |
10 software programs "owners", most of whom aim to withhold software's | |
11 potential benefit from the rest of the public. They would like to be | |
12 the only ones who can copy and modify the software that we use. | |
13 | |
14 The copyright system grew up with printing--a technology for mass | |
15 production copying. Copyright fit in well with this technology | |
16 because it restricted only the mass producers of copies. It did not | |
17 take freedom away from readers of books. An ordinary reader, who did | |
18 not own a printing press, could copy books only with pen and ink, and | |
19 few readers were sued for that. | |
20 | |
21 Digital technology is more flexible than the printing press: when | |
22 information has digital form, you can easily copy it to share it with | |
23 others. This very flexibility makes a bad fit with a system like | |
24 copyright. That's the reason for the increasingly nasty and draconian | |
25 measures now used to enforce software copyright. Consider these four | |
26 practices of the Software Publishers Association (SPA): | |
27 | |
28 * Massive propaganda saying it is wrong to disobey the owners | |
29 to help your friend. | |
30 | |
31 * Solicitation for stool pigeons to inform on their coworkers and | |
32 colleagues. | |
33 | |
34 * Raids (with police help) on offices and schools, in which people are | |
35 told they must prove they are innocent of illegal copying. | |
36 | |
37 * Prosecution (by the US government, at the SPA's request) of people | |
38 such as MIT's David LaMacchia, not for copying software (he is not | |
39 accused of copying any), but merely for leaving copying facilities | |
40 unguarded and failing to censor their use. | |
41 | |
42 All four practices resemble those used in the former Soviet Union, | |
43 where every copying machine had a guard to prevent forbidden copying, | |
44 and where individuals had to copy information secretly and pass it | |
45 from hand to hand as "samizdat". There is of course a difference: the | |
46 motive for information control in the Soviet Union was political; in | |
47 the US the motive is profit. But it is the actions that affect us, | |
48 not the motive. Any attempt to block the sharing of information, no | |
49 matter why, leads to the same methods and the same harshness. | |
50 | |
51 Owners make several kinds of arguments for giving them the power | |
52 to control how we use information: | |
53 | |
54 * Name calling. | |
55 | |
56 Owners use smear words such as "piracy" and "theft", as well as expert | |
57 terminology such as "intellectual property" and "damage", to suggest a | |
58 certain line of thinking to the public--a simplistic analogy between | |
59 programs and physical objects. | |
60 | |
61 Our ideas and intuitions about property for material objects are about | |
62 whether it is right to *take an object away* from someone else. They | |
63 don't directly apply to *making a copy* of something. But the owners | |
64 ask us to apply them anyway. | |
65 | |
66 * Exaggeration. | |
67 | |
68 Owners say that they suffer "harm" or "economic loss" when users copy | |
69 programs themselves. But the copying has no direct effect on the | |
70 owner, and it harms no one. The owner can lose only if the person who | |
71 made the copy would otherwise have paid for one from the owner. | |
72 | |
73 A little thought shows that most such people would not have bought | |
74 copies. Yet the owners compute their "losses" as if each and every | |
75 one would have bought a copy. That is exaggeration--to put it kindly. | |
76 | |
77 * The law. | |
78 | |
79 Owners often describe the current state of the law, and the harsh | |
80 penalties they can threaten us with. Implicit in this approach is the | |
81 suggestion that today's law reflects an unquestionable view of | |
82 morality--yet at the same time, we are urged to regard these penalties | |
83 as facts of nature that can't be blamed on anyone. | |
84 | |
85 This line of persuasion isn't designed to stand up to critical | |
86 thinking; it's intended to reinforce a habitual mental pathway. | |
87 | |
88 It's elemental that laws don't decide right and wrong. Every American | |
89 should know that, forty years ago, it was against the law in many | |
90 states for a black person to sit in the front of a bus; but only | |
91 racists would say sitting there was wrong. | |
92 | |
93 * Natural rights. | |
94 | |
95 Authors often claim a special connection with programs they have | |
96 written, and go on to assert that, as a result, their desires and | |
97 interests concerning the program simply outweigh those of anyone | |
98 else--or even those of the whole rest of the world. (Typically | |
99 companies, not authors, hold the copyrights on software, but we are | |
100 expected to ignore this discrepancy.) | |
101 | |
102 To those who propose this as an ethical axiom--the author is more | |
103 important than you--I can only say that I, a notable software author | |
104 myself, call it bunk. | |
105 | |
106 But people in general are only likely to feel any sympathy with the | |
107 natural rights claims for two reasons. | |
108 | |
109 One reason is an overstretched analogy with material objects. When I | |
110 cook spaghetti, I do object if someone else takes it and stops me from | |
111 eating it. In this case, that person and I have the same material | |
112 interests at stake, and it's a zero-sum game. The smallest | |
113 distinction between us is enough to tip the ethical balance. | |
114 | |
115 But whether you run or change a program I wrote affects you directly | |
116 and me only indirectly. Whether you give a copy to your friend | |
117 affects you and your friend much more than it affects me. I shouldn't | |
118 have the power to tell you not to do these things. No one should. | |
119 | |
120 The second reason is that people have been told that natural rights | |
121 for authors is the accepted and unquestioned tradition of our society. | |
122 | |
123 As a matter of history, the opposite is true. The idea of natural | |
124 rights of authors was proposed and decisively rejected when the US | |
125 Constitution was drawn up. That's why the Constitution only *permits* | |
126 a system of copyright and does not *require* one; that's why it says | |
127 that copyright must be temporary. It also states that the purpose of | |
128 copyright is to promote progress--not to reward authors. Copyright | |
129 does reward authors somewhat, and publishers more, but that is | |
130 intended as a means of modifying their behavior. | |
131 | |
132 The real established tradition of our society is that copyright cuts | |
133 into the natural rights of the public--and that this can only be | |
134 justified for the public's sake. | |
135 | |
136 * Economics. | |
137 | |
138 The final argument made for having owners of software is that this | |
139 leads to production of more software. | |
140 | |
141 Unlike the others, this argument at least takes a legitimate approach | |
142 to the subject. It is based on a valid goal--satisfying the users of | |
143 software. And it is empirically clear that people will produce more of | |
144 something if they are well paid for doing so. | |
145 | |
146 But the economic argument has a flaw: it is based on the assumption | |
147 that the difference is only a matter of how much money we have to pay. | |
148 It assumes that "production of software" is what we want, whether the | |
149 software has owners or not. | |
150 | |
151 People readily accept this assumption because it accords with our | |
152 experiences with material objects. Consider a sandwich, for instance. | |
153 You might well be able to get an equivalent sandwich either free or | |
154 for a price. If so, the amount you pay is the only difference. | |
155 Whether or not you have to buy it, the sandwich has the same taste, | |
156 the same nutritional value, and in either case you can only eat it | |
157 once. Whether you get the sandwich from an owner or not cannot | |
158 directly affect anything but the amount of money you have afterwards. | |
159 | |
160 This is true for any kind of material object--whether or not it has an | |
161 owner does not directly affect what it *is*, or what you can do with | |
162 it if you acquire it. | |
163 | |
164 But if a program has an owner, this very much affects what it is, and | |
165 what you can do with a copy if you buy one. The difference is not | |
166 just a matter of money. The system of owners of software encourages | |
167 software owners to produce something--but not what society really | |
168 needs. And it causes intangible ethical pollution that affects us | |
169 all. | |
170 | |
171 What does society need? It needs information that is truly available | |
172 to its citizens--for example, programs that people can read, fix, | |
173 adapt, and improve, not just operate. But what software owners | |
174 typically deliver is a black box that we can't study or change. | |
175 | |
176 Society also needs freedom. When a program has an owner, the users | |
177 lose freedom to control part of their own lives. | |
178 | |
179 And above all society needs to encourage the spirit of voluntary | |
180 cooperation in its citizens. When software owners tell us that | |
181 helping our neighbors in a natural way is "piracy", they pollute our | |
182 society's civic spirit. | |
183 | |
184 This is why we say that free software is a matter of freedom, not | |
185 price. | |
186 | |
187 The economic argument for owners is erroneous, but the economic issue | |
188 is real. Some people write useful software for the pleasure of | |
189 writing it or for admiration and love; but if we want more software | |
190 than those people write, we need to raise funds. | |
191 | |
192 For ten years now, free software developers have tried various methods | |
193 of finding funds, with some success. There's no need to make anyone | |
194 rich; the median US family income, around $35k, proves to be enough | |
195 incentive for many jobs that are less satisfying than programming. | |
196 | |
197 For years, until a fellowship made it unnecessary, I made a living | |
198 from custom enhancements of the free software I had written. Each | |
199 enhancement was added to the standard released version and thus | |
200 eventually became available to the general public. Clients paid me so | |
201 that I would work on the enhancements they wanted, rather than on the | |
202 features I would otherwise have considered highest priority. | |
203 | |
204 The Free Software Foundation, a tax-exempt charity for free software | |
205 development, raises funds by selling CD-ROMs, tapes and manuals (all | |
206 of which users are free to copy and change), as well as from | |
207 donations. It now has a staff of five programmers, plus three | |
208 employees who handle mail orders. | |
209 | |
210 Some free software developers make money by selling support services. | |
211 Cygnus Support, with around 50 employees, estimates that about 15 per | |
212 cent of its staff activity is free software development--a respectable | |
213 percentage for a software company. | |
214 | |
215 Companies including Intel, Motorola, Texas Instruments and Analog | |
216 Devices have combined to fund the continued development of the free | |
217 GNU compiler for the language C. Meanwhile, the GNU compiler for the | |
218 Ada language is being funded by the US Air Force, which believes this | |
219 is the most cost-effective way to get a high quality compiler. | |
220 | |
221 All these examples are small; the free software movement is still | |
222 small, and still young. But the example of listener-supported radio | |
223 in this country shows it's possible to support a large activity | |
224 without forcing each user to pay. | |
225 | |
226 As a computer user today, you may find yourself using a proprietary | |
227 program. If your friend asks to make a copy, it would be wrong to | |
228 refuse. Cooperation is more important than copyright. But | |
229 underground, closet cooperation does not make for a good society. A | |
230 person should aspire to live an upright life openly with pride, and | |
231 this means saying "No" to proprietary software. | |
232 | |
233 You deserve to be able to cooperate openly and freely with other | |
234 people who use software. You deserve to be able to learn how the | |
235 software works, and to teach your students with it. You deserve to be | |
236 able to hire your favorite programmer to fix it when it breaks. | |
237 | |
238 You deserve free software. | |
239 | |
240 | |
241 Copyright 1994 Richard Stallman | |
242 Verbatim copying and redistribution is permitted | |
243 without royalty as long as this notice is preserved; | |
244 alteration is not permitted. |